One of the most important factors that inhibited the study of praxeology for the last 60 years was Friedrich Hayek's argument that praxeology is inapplicable to the study of market phenomena. His argument against praxeology (which he called the "Pure Logic of Choice") is relatively simple. The pure logic of choice, as Hayek understood it, entails an analytical relationship between (1) the object of an actor's action, and (2) the actor's action. Here is the key passage from Hayek's essay "The Facts of the Social Sciences":
From the fact that whenever we interpret human action as in any sense purposive or meaningful, whether we do so in ordinary life or for the purposes of the social sciences, we have to define both the objects of human activity and the different kinds of actions themselves, not in physical terms but in terms of the opinions or intentions of the acting persons, there follow some very important consequences; namely, nothing less than that we can, from the concepts of the objects, analytically conclude something about what the actions will be. If we define an object in terms of a person's attitude toward it, it follows, of course, that the definition of the object implies a statement about the attitude of the person toward the thing. When we say that a person possesses food or money, or that he utters a word, we imply that he knows that the first can be eaten, that the second can be used to buy something with, and that the third can be understood — and perhaps many other things.
Hayek's conception of praxeology or the pure logic of choice is a kind of conceptual analysis. If we say the object confronting the actor is food, we can analytically conclude that the actionassociated with that object will be eating. If the object confronting the actor is money, we can analytically conclude that the action associated with that object will be buying or selling, etc. Thus, Hayek conceives an analytic or logically necessary relationship between (1) the object that we, as social scientists, assume confronts an actor, and (2) the action the actor will perform based on the assumption of the object that confronts that actor. We can see that the analytic relationship Hayek conceives is between an object appearing to an observed or studied actor, and the action that must, by conceptual analysis, "accompany" that object.
Hayek then makes the following point. The market is comprised of the interactions of a number of people. When we study the market, we study the relationship between of a number of people, notan individual actor and the relationship between his action and the object of his action.
Here are the relevant passages from Hayek's essay "Economics and Knowledge":
I have long felt that the concept of equilibrium itself and the methods which we employ in pure analysis have a clear meaning only when confined to the analysis of the action of a single person and that we are really passing into a different sphere and silently introducing a new element of altogether different character when we apply it to the explanation of the interactions of a number of different individuals.…The sense in which we use the concept of equilibrium to describe the interdependence of the different actions of one person does not immediately admit of application to the relations between actions of different people.
To get a clear idea of Hayek's point, let us consider ourselves social scientists looking at a local marketplace from the top of a nearby building. We see many people in the marketplace interacting: buying, selling, talking, eating, etc. To each of these individual actors, the pure logic of choice, as described above, applies. If one actor has food, the action analytically associated with this is eating; if one actor has money, the action analytically associated with this is buying, etc.
But this method of analysis does not apply to the relationship between actors. If one actor has food, this doesn't say anything about the action of a second, different actor.
Thus, the pure logic of choice (praxeology) does not apply to study of the market.
This argument of Hayek's constitutes the fundamental difference between the Misesian and the Hayekian conception of economics. The fundamental proposition of Hayekian economics is that market study can only be empirical, not a priori. In other words, praxeology is inapplicable to market study:
What I see only now clearly is the problem of my relationship to Mises, which began with my 1937 article on the economics of knowledge, which was an attempt to persuade Mises himself that when he asserted that the market theory was a priori, he was wrong; that what was a priori was only the logic of individual action, but the moment that you passed from this to the interaction of many people, you entered into the empirical field. (Hayek on Hayek, p. 72)
As Hayek's argument against praxeology is relatively simple, so is it simple to see the flaw in Hayek's argument. We may ask, when a marketplace is the object of the actor's action (when the actor observes a market, or when he walks in a market, or when he buys in a market) why can't we draw an analytical conclusion from this object of the actor's action? Or, when a price is the object of the actor's action (when the actor observes a price, or asks a price, or pays a price), why can't we draw an analytical conclusion from this object of the actor's action? In short, why can't we arrive at analytical conclusions regarding any social object or social phenomenon or any market object or market phenomenon, by understanding them to be objects of an actor's action, and drawing analytical conclusions from these objects as Hayek indicates?
If we say an actor possess food, and from this we may analytically arrive at the action eating, then when the actor visits a market, why may we not analytically arrive at the action shopping? And when the actor considers a price, why may we not analytically arrive at the action purchasing?
By the terms of Hayek's own conception of praxeology it would seem this analytical method should be applicable to the objects or phenomena of the market, and this would constitute "a priori" analysis of the market.
Furthermore, this same procedure should be applicable to other social objects and social phenomena such as languages, laws, families, etc.
One other important aspect of Hayek's critique should be noted. Recall that when Hayek describes the procedure of the pure logic of choice, he does so in terms of a third-person narrative. Hayek writes,
When we say that a person possesses food or money, or that he utters a word, we imply that he knows that the first can be eaten, that the second can be used to buy something with, and that the third can be understood — and perhaps many other things. (emphasis added)
Hayek here refers to a hypothetical actor whom the scientist observes or studies. The question is, what about the case when it is the social scientist himself who interacts with the object or phenomenon in question? Let's say that the social scientist visits a farmer's market or pays a price for something in this same market, or pays interest on a loan. Because the market, the price, the loan, and the interest, appear to the scientist as objects of his own action, what prevents the scientist from drawing analytical conclusions about action from these objects that appear to him? Is there something that obligates the social scientist to study only the relationship between the objects and actions of other people? What prevents the scientist from studying the relationship between his own actions and the objects of his actions?
Thus, there are two problems with Hayek's critique of praxeology:
- Hayek doesn't explain why the pure logic of choice can't be applied to study of the market, by considering market phenomena as objects of action (visiting a market, paying a price, etc.) and then drawing analytical conclusions from the concepts of those objects.
- Hayek doesn't explain why the social scientist can't draw analytical conclusions about the relationship between his own actions and the objects of his actions.
As should be clear, these are problems in the application and understanding of Hayek's own conception of praxeology. Above, we assume that Hayek's conception of praxeology is valid and is the same as Mises's, and we simply ask "if praxeology applies to objects a, b, and c, why doesn't praxeology apply to objects x, y, and z?" And we ask "if praxeology applies to the objects of A's action, why doesn't praxeology apply to the objects of B's action?" Hayek agrees that it is possible to draw analytical conclusions from objects a, b, and c by considering them objects of the action of actor A. We simply ask why we can't draw analytical conclusions from objects x, y, and z by considering them objects of the action of actor B? We're asking why Hayek's principles don't apply to objects and persons besides the specific ones Hayek uses to illustrate his principles.
It should be noted though that Hayek's conception of the pure logic of choice is not identical to Mises's conception of praxeology. Hayek's pure logic of choice is a kind of conceptual analysis. Misesian praxeology is not concerned with conceptual analysis per se; it is concerned with the formal structure of action. These two things are not necessarily the same. As Mises conceives things,
Praxeology is not concerned with the changing content of acting, but with its pure form and its categorial structure. (Human Action)
Thus, as soon as we differentiate the object of action "food" from the object of action "money" (as Hayek does in the pure logic of choice), we are, according to Mises, referring to the changing content of action, and have therefore left praxeology proper.
This shows that Hayek conceives praxeology differently from Mises.
Aside from the questions about the application of Hayek's pure logic of choice, there are serious questions about the knowledge that it could possibly attain.
Recall, for example, that Hayek claims,
We can, from the concepts of the objects, analytically conclude something about what the actions will be.
Is this simple proposition necessarily true? Can we analytically conclude the action of the individual based on the concept of the object that confronts him?
If we say that an actor possesses food, does this mean that the actor will perform the action of eating? Can't an actor possess food but not eat the food? Let's say an actor possesses a ball. Must he throw the ball? If an actor possesses a ball, may we "analytically conclude something about what the actions will be"? The answer seems clearly to be no. Perhaps we can analytically conclude that if an actor possesses a ball, then he also possesses a sphere and an object having an internal volume, etc. Here we have conceptual or tautological analysis, but we have not thereby established a necessary relationship between a particular object and a particular action that an actor possessing that object must perform. The study of concepts is not necessarily identical to the study of action.
Conclusion
One of the fundamental pillars of Hayekian social thought is Hayek's contention that study of the market cannot be a priori. But Hayek seems not to have realized the implications of his own conception of the pure logic of choice. He didn't realize that the method of logical analysis he envisioned could easily be applied to the market and its various objects and phenomena (prices, interest, etc.).
In conceiving that formal exact science is inapplicable to the study of market phenomena, Hayek's thinking diverges not only from Mises's, but from Menger's as well. Menger'sInvestigations into the Method of the Social Sciences is largely devoted to the proposition that formal exact science is valid in all realms of the world of phenomena, "economy" being but one realm of human phenomena. Thus, Mises's insight that economics is only one branch of praxeology can be traced back to Menger's vision of the "exact approach to cognition." In his Investigations, Menger provided a definition of formal exact science, a science that Mises later termed praxeology:
The aim of this orientation, which in the future we will call the exact one, an aim which research pursues in the same way in all realms of the world of phenomena, is the determination of strict laws of phenomena, of regularities in the succession of phenomena which do not present themselves to us as absolute, but which in respect to the approaches to cognition by which we attain to them simply bear within themselves the guarantee of absoluteness. It is the determination of laws of phenomena which commonly are called "laws of nature," but more correctly should be designated by the expression "exact laws."
No comments:
Post a Comment
Your Comments